On Becoming Fearful Quickly: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle’s Somatic Model of Socratean akrasia.

Authors

  • Brian Andrew Lightbody Brock University

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p134-161

Keywords:

Akrasia (weakness of will), Somatic, Socratic Moral Psychology, Aristotle, Drunken Analogy

Abstract

The Protagoras is the touchstone of Socrates’ moral intellectualist stance. The position in a nutshell stipulates that the proper reevaluation of a desire is enough to neutralize it.[1] The implication of this position is that akrasia or weakness of will is not the result of desire (or fear for that matter) overpowering reason but is due to ignorance.  

Socrates’ eliminativist position on weakness of will, however, flies in the face of the common-sense experience regarding akratic action and thus Aristotle was at pains to render Socrates’ account of moral incontinence intelligible. The key improvement Aristotle makes to Socrates’s model is to underscore that the conditioning of the akratic’s body plays a critical role in determining the power of one’s appetites and, accordingly, the capacity of one to resist the temptations these appetites present for rational evaluation.  As Aristotle puts it, “For the incontinent man is like the people who get drunk quickly and on little wine, i.e., on less than most people.” (1151a 3-4). Aristotle presents what I shall call a somatic paradigm (i.e. the drunkard analogy) in order to tackle the problem of akrasia and it is this somatic solution that marks a significant improvement over Socrates’s intellectualist or informational model or so the tradition tells us.

In this paper, I wish to push back on the above Aristotelian explanation. I argue that when one fully examines Socrates’ account of weakness of will that Aristotle’s solution is less effective than is traditionally thought. In fact, Socrates can bring Aristotle’s model into his own; just as Aristotle absorbs what is right about Socrates’s model, namely, that akratic action utilizes reason but to a limited degree, Socrates in Meno (77C-78A) develops his own somatic model of weakness of will that connects to the intellectualist paradigm of the Protagoras.   To achieve this rapprochement between the two models, I zero in on the description provided by Socrates of those individuals who desire bad things knowing they are bad as “ill-starred” or “bad spirited” (κακοδαίμων ). The “bad-spirited” is the coward and, in contrast to Aristotle’s drunkard, becomes fearful quickly from little danger. This additional somatic component, when connected to Socrates’s position on akrasia in Protagoras adds a new twist to Socrates’s model in the following way: while no one wishes to be ill-starred such that more harm than good will befall one, one may become so as a result of the bad choices one knowingly makes.

 

[1] “After him came Socrates, who spoke better and further about this subject, but even he was not successful. For he used to make the virtues into sciences, and this is impossible. For the sciences all involve reason, and reason is to be found in the intellectual part of the soul. So that all the virtues, according to him arise in the rational part of the soul. The result is that in making the virtues into sciences he is doing away with the nonrational part of the soul and is thereby doing away with passion and character…” (Aristotle, Magna Moralia 1.1. 1182 a15-26)

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

References

Aristotle. The Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. W.D. Ross in The Basic Works of Aristotle. Ed Richard McKeon, New York: Random House 1941.

Brickhouse. Thomas and Smith, Nicholas. Socratic Moral Psychology, Cambridge U.K: Cambridge University Press 2010.

Brickhouse, Thomas and Smith, Nicholas. “Socrates on the Emotions”, PLATO journal Vol 15. 2015, 9-28.

Crombie, I. M. 1962. An Examination of Plato’s Doctrines. Vol. 1. London. Rudebusch, George.

Davidson, Donald. “How is Weakness of Will Possible”, in Essays on Actions and Events, Philosophical Essays, Vol. 1. Oxford University Press 2001.

Devin, Henry. ARISTOTLE ON PLEASURE AND THE WORST FORM OF AKRASIA Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5: 255–270, 2002.

Dewey, John. “The Theory of Emotion.” Psychological Review 1 (1894): 553–6 https://doi.org/10.1037/h0069054

Dimos, Panos. “Good and Pleasure in the Protagoras” Ancient Philosophy Vol. 28, 2008, 253-284.

Gosling, Justin. “Mad, Drunk or Asleep, Aristotle’s Akratic.” Phronesis 1993. Vol. XXXVIII/I, 98-104

Hare, R.M. Freedom and Reason Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1963.

Hippocrates. The Genuine Works of Hippocrates. Trans. Charles Darwin Adams. New York. Dover. 1868.

Irwin, T.H. Plato’s Ethics Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995

Irwin, Terrence. “Aristotle Reads the Protagoras” Weakness of Will from Plato to the Present (Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy Volume 49) Washington D.C. Catholic University of America Press, 2011. 22-41.

Lightbody, Brian. Dispersing the Clouds of Temptation: Turning Away from Weakness of will and Turning Towards the Sun. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock 2015.

Mele, Alfred. Backsliding: Understanding Weakness of Will, New York: Oxford University

Nielsen, Karen Margrethe “Deliberation and Decision in the Magna Moralia and Eudemian Ethics” in Virtue, Happiness and Knowledge: Themes from the work of Gail Fine and Terence Irwin Eds Brink, Meyer, Shields Oxford Oxford University Press, 2018, 1-25

Penner, Terry. “Socrates and the Early Dialogues ”.The Cambridge Companion to Plato, Richard Kraut Ed. Cambridge U.K: Cambridge University Press, 1992, 121-169.

Penner, Terry. “Knowledge vs. True Belief in the Socratic Psychology of Action”.Apeiron, 3 1996, 199-230.

Plato. Protagoras Plato the Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper, trans. Stanley Lombardo and Karen Bell. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing 1997

Plato, Gorgias. Plato the Complete Works ed. John M. Cooper Trans. Donald Zeyl. . Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing 1997

Plato, Meno and Other Dialogues(Charmides, Laches, Lysis), trans. Robert Waterfield. Oxford University Press 2005

Reshotko, Naomi. Socrates Virtue: Making the Best of the Neither-Good-Nor-Bad. Cambridge University Press 2006.

Roochnik, David. “Aristotle's Account of the Vicious: A Forgivable Inconsistency” History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol. 24, No. 3 (Jul., 2007), pp. 207-220

Rorty, A.O. (ed.), “Akrasia and Pleasure”, in Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. Berkeley: University of California Press 1980, pp. 267–284

Stalley, R.F. “Plato’s Argument for the Division of the Reasoning and Appetitive Elements within the Soul”, Phronesis20.2 (1975) 110-128.

Vlastos, Gregory. Introduction. In Plato: “Protagoras,” trans. Benjamin Jowett, rev. Martin Ostwald, vii–lviii. Indianapolis, 1956.

Wilburn, Josh. “Plato’s Protagoras The Hedonist” Classical Philology 113 (3) 2016 224-244,

Xenophon, Xenophon in Seven Volumes, 3. Trans. Carleton L. Brownson. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA; William Heinemann, Ltd., London. 1922.

Downloads

Published

2023-10-31

Issue

Section

Articles

How to Cite

Lightbody, B. A. (2023). On Becoming Fearful Quickly: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle’s Somatic Model of Socratean akrasia . Journal of Ancient Philosophy, 17(2), 134-161. https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p134-161